Tuesday, October 7, 2014

Neuroaesthetics, a new discipline?

“Neuroaesthetics”, a field which has just recently been explored by some more adventurous neuroscientists, is an attempt to explain the human experience of art, and particularly the appreciation of some art pieces over others, in terms of cognitive mechanisms. John Hyman, Professor of philosophy at Oxford, recently argued in his piece “Art and Neuroscience” that the “neuro-aesthetics” proposed by the two main theorists in the field, V.S. Ramachandran and Semir Zeki, fail on numerous levels, such as improper translation from animal experiments to human experience, failure to distinguish the art object from other kinds of pleasurable objects (a difficult task but one long thought essential to aesthetic theory), and, most importantly, a narrow or otherwise unworkable definition of art itself. Hyman thinks these difficulties stem from a failure to build upon existing aesthetic theories.[1] When looking at the two scientists’ definitions of art, it is easy to see where he is coming from, Ramachandran’s view is essentially that all art is caricature, and Zeki believes that all “great art” is defined by its capacity for multiple interpretations. As Hyman puts it at the end of his article, “In neuroscience, and in psychology in general, philosophy is unavoidable; and if we ignore the philosophy of the past, we shall simply reinvent the wheel. In other words, our ideas will be based on mediocre and amateurish philosophy of our own.” And, what may well be worse, these theories create a model of a universal viewer, utterly ignoring gender, sex, and other forms of social positionality.

One of the principle problems with these neuroscientific approaches to aesthetic theory is that even if they could effectively explain the mechanisms by which human beings enjoy art, they would still be providing a “how” answer, when at least part of the question in aesthetics is always a “why”. For instance, Patrick Cavanaugh, in his article “The artist as neuroscientist” for Nature Neuroscience[2] claims that a recent study by Vuilleumier et al.[3] which demonstrated that blurry faces activated the amygdala more than sharpened or unfiltered versions perhaps demonstrates why impressionist paintings can be so emotionally evocative, when a photograph of the same scene seems unlikely to do the same. While it may be unscientific for Cavanaugh to make this leap, his story is somewhat plausible, but even if we take it to be true, the question remains, why do we like this? What about deriving an emotional experience from an art object is pleasurable?

An even bigger and more basic problem—which seems to have gone largely undiscussed—with these recent neuro-aesthetic theories is that they assume that a single piece of art’s quality can be expressed with a single explanation. In other words, they seem to be utterly unaware of the role of positionality in the perception and enjoyment of art. This is particularly obvious in Ramachandran’s chosen example of his proposed peak-shift (see figure and comment for explanation) effect, which is the exaggerated sex characteristics of classical sculptures of Indian goddesses. But one also has to ask, what exactly would Ramachandran’s explanation be for a straight woman or gay man who likes these sculptures? Zeki fails on similar grounds, seemingly failing to consider at all how the multiplicity of interpretations is dependent largely upon the viewer’s social position.


The peak-shift effect as demonstrated by pigeons pecking in response to different light wavelengths in H.M. Hanson’s experiment. The birds are first conditioned by being rewarded for one stimulus (sD) and not for another (sΔ), but then when shown a range of stimuli, they tend to overestimate the difference between the stimuli for which they are rewarded and that which they are not, causing the response peak to be “shifted” away from the reward stimulus.[4]  


Hyman argues that neuroscience, with its origins in 19th century modes of thought and a philosophy of perception inherited from Locke and Kant is unlikely to succeed in the field of aesthetics without acknowledging its heritage. A number of 20th century philosophers went further, arguing that art is precisely the thing which the scientific worldview cannot encapsulate. I am not willing to go that far. I think there is ample commonality between art and science, they are both ways of making sense of experience via observing and manipulating the world, so both are fundamentally exploratory. Interestingly, Cavanaugh makes a point about how the un-naturalistic but still readily visually acceptable uses of space and light in renaissance and baroque painting indicate how the visual system functions; while this same piece of evidence is used by cultural critics construct psychoanalytic meanings.  I think that explanations of neural mechanisms definitely have a promising place in aesthetics, but first we must understand more about the brain in general, and particularly the interrelated neural and social differences between viewers, and that these explanations will be much more useful if they are incorporated into the existing discipline rather than used to build a new one. 

                                                                                                                                                                       -Nathaniel Tingley





[1] Hyman, John. (2010) R. Frigg, M.C. Hunter (eds.), Beyond Mimesis and Convention, Boston Studies 245
in the Philosophy of Science 262.
[2] Cavanagh, P. (2005). The artist as neuroscientist. Nature, 434(7031), 301-307. doi:10.1038/434301a
[3] Vuilleumier, P., Armony J. L., Driver, J. & Dolan R. J. (2003). Nature Neurosci 6, 624-631.
[4] Hanson, H. M. (1959). "Effects of discrimination training on stimulus generalization". Journal of Experimental Psychology 58: 321–334.

No comments:

Post a Comment